The following theorem asserts that inequivalent valuations are in fact
almost totally indepedent. For our purposes it will be superseded by
the strong approximation theorem (Theorem 20.4.4).
Proof.
We note first that it will be enough to find, for each
, an
element
such that
where
. For then as
, we have
It is then enough to take
By symmetry it is enough to show the existence of with
We will do this by induction on
.
First suppose . Since
and
are
inequivalent (and all absolute values are assumed nontrivial)
there is an such that
and |
(16.2) |
and similarly a
such that
and
Then
will do.
Remark 16.3.2
It is not completely clear that
one can choose an
such that (
16.3.1) is satisfied.
Suppose it were impossible. Then because the valuations are
nontrivial, we would have that for any
if
then
. This implies the converse statement: if
and
then
. To see this, suppose there
is an
such that
and
.
Choose
such that
. Then for any integer
we have
, so by hypothesis
. Thus
for all
. Since
we
have
as
, so
, a
contradiction since
. Thus
if and only if
, and we have proved before that this implies that
is equivalent to
.
Next suppose . By the case , there is an such
that
By the case for
there is a
such that
and
Then put
where
is sufficiently large so that
and
for
.
Example 16.3.3
Suppose
, let
be the archimedean absolute value
and let
be the
-adic absolute value. Let
,
, and
, as in the remark right after
Theorem
16.3.1. Then the theorem implies that there
is an element
such that
and
As in the proof of the theorem, we can find such a
by finding
a
such that
and
, and
a
and
. For example,
and
works, since
and
and
and
. Again
following the proof, we see that for sufficiently large
we can take
We have
,
,
,
,
,
. None of the
work for
,
but
works.